IMAGE DESCRIPTION:
Hey, Vsauce. Michael here. What is the biggest number you can think of? A googol? A googolplex? A milinillion?... olplex? Well, in reality, the biggest number is 40. Covering more than 12,000 square meters of earth, this 40, made out of strategically planted trees in Russia, is larger than the battalion markers on Signal Hill in Calgary, the 6 found on the bobbin badges in England, even the mile of pi Brady unrolled on numberphile. 40 is the biggest number... on Earth in terms of surface area. But in terms of amount of things, which is normally what we mean by a number being big, 40 probably isn't the biggest. For example, there's 41. And, well, and then there's 42, and 43, a billion, a trillion... You know, no matter how big of a number you can think of, you can always go higher. So there is no biggest last number. Except... infinity? No. Infinity is not a number. Instead, it's a kind of number. You need infinite numbers to talk about and compare amounts that are unending. But some unending amounts, some infinities, are literally bigger than others. Let's visit some of them and count past them. First things first. When a number refers to how many things there are, it is called a cardinal number. For example, 4 bananas. 12 flags. 20 dots. 20 is the cardinality of this set of dots. Now, 2 sets have the same cardinality when they contain the same number of things. We can demonstrate this equality by comparing each member of one set, one to one, with each member of the other. Same cardinality; pretty simple. We use the natural numbers, that is, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, and so on, as cardinals. Whenever we talk about how many things there are. But how many natural numbers are there? It can't be some number in the naturals because there'd always be 1+that number after it. Instead, there's a unique name for this amount: Aleph null. Aleph is the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet, and aleph null is the first smallest infinity. It's how many natural numbers there are. It's also how many even numbers there are. How many odd numbers there are. It's also how many rational numbers, that is, fractions, there are. That may sound surprising, since fractions appear more numerous on the number line. But as Cantor showed, there's a way to arrange every single possible rational such that the naturals can be put into a one to one correspondence with them. They have the same cardinality. Point is, aleph null is a big amount. Bigger than any finite amount. A googol? A googolplex? A googolplex factorial to the power of a googolplex to a googolplex squared? Times Graham's number? Aleph null is bigger. But we can count past it. How? Well, let's use our old friend: the Supertask. If we draw a bunch of lines and make each next line a fraction of the size and a fraction of the distance from each last line, well, we can fit an unending number of lines into a finite space. The number of lines here is equal to the number of natural numbers there are. The two can be matched one to one. There's always a next natural, but there's also always a next line. Both sets have the cardinality aleph null. But what happens when I do this? Now how many lines are there? Aleph null + 1? No. Unending amounts aren't like finite amounts. There are still only aleph null lines here because I can match the naturals one to one just like before. I just start here and then continue from the beginning. Clearly, the amount of lines hasn't changed. I can even add 2 more lines. 3 more. 4 more. I always end up with only aleph null things. I can even add another infinite aleph null of lines and still not change the quantity. Every even number can compare with these, and every odd number with these. There is still a line for every natural. Another cool way to see that these lines don't add to the total is to show that you can make this same sequence without drawing new lines at all. Just take every other line and move them all together to the end. It's the same thing. But hold on a second. This and this may have the same number of things in them, but clearly there's something different about them, right? I mean if it's not how many things they're made of, what is it? Well, let's go back to having just 1 line after an aleph null sized collection. What if, instead of matching the naturals one to one, we insist on numbering each line according to the order it was drawn in? So we have to start here, and number left to right. Now, what number does this line get? In the realm of the infinite, labelling things in order is pretty different than counting them. You see, this line doesn't contribute to the total, but in able to label it according to the order it appeared in, well, we need a set of labels of numbers that extends past the naturals. We need ordinal numbers. The first trans finite ordinal is omega, the lowercase Greek letter omega. This isn't a joke or a trick, it's literally just the next label you'll need after using up the infinite collection of every single counting number first. If you got omega-th place in a race, that would mean that an infinite number of people finished the race, and then you did. After omega comes omega+1, which doesn't really look like a number, but it is, just like 2 or 12 or or 800. Then comes omega+2, omega+3... Ordinal numbers label things in order. Ordinals aren't about how many things there are. Instead, they tell us how those things are arranged; their order type. The order type of a set is just the first ordinal number not needed to label everything in the set in order. So, for finite numbers, cardinality and order type are the same. The order type of all the naturals is omega. The order type of this sequence is omega+1, and now it's omega+2. No matter how long an arrangement becomes, as long as it's well ordered, as long as every part of it contains a beginning element, the whole thing describes a new ordinal number. Always. This will be very important later on. It should be noted at this point that if you are ever playing a game of "who can name the biggest number," and you were considering saying "omega+1," you should be careful. Your opponents might require the number you named to be a cardinal that refers to an amount. These numbers refer to the same amount of stuff, just arranged differently. Omega+1 isn't bigger than omega, it just comes after omega. But aleph null isn't the end. Why? Well, because it can be shown that there are infinities bugger than aleph null. That literally contain more things. One of the best ways to do this is with Cantor's Diagonal Argument. In my episode on the Banach-Tarski Paradox, I used it to show that the number of real numbers is larger than the number of natural numbers. But for the purposes of this video, let's focus on another thing bigger than aleph null: the powerset of aleph null. The powerset of a set is the set of all the different subsets you can make from it. For example, from the set of 1 and 2, I can make a set of nothing, or 1, or 2, or 1 and 2. The power set of 1, 2, 3 is the empty set, 1, and 2, and 3, and 1 and 2, and 1 and 3, and 2 and 3, and 1, 2, 3. As you can see, a powerset contains many more members than the original set. 2 to the power of however many members the original set had, to be exact. So, what's the powerset of all the naturals? Well, let's see. Imagine a list of every natural number. Cool. Now, the subset of all, say, even numbers would look like this. Yes, no, yes, no, yes, no, and so on. The subset of all odd numbers would look like this. Here's the subset of just 3, 7, and 12. And how about every number except 5? Or no number except 5? Obviously, this list of subsets is going to be, well, infinite. But imagine matching them all, one to one, with a natural. If, even then, there's a way to keep producing new subsets that are clearly not listed anywhere here, we will know that we've got a set with more members than there are natural numbers. A bigger infinity than aleph null. The way to do this is to start up here in the first subset and just do the opposite of what we see. 0 is a member of this one, so our new set will not contain 0. Next, move diagonally down 1s membership in the second subset. 1 is a member of it, so it will not be in our new one. 2 is not in the third subset, so it will be in ours, and so on. As you can see, we are describing a subset that will be, by definition, different in at least one way from every single other subset on this aleph null sized list. Even if we put this new subset back in, diagonalization can still be done. The powerset of the naturals will always resist a one to one correspondence with the naturals. It's an infinity bigger than aleph null. Repeated applications of powerset will produce sets that can't be put into one to one correspondence with the last. So it's a great way to quickly produce bigger and bigger infinities. The point is, there are more cardinals after aleph null. Let's try to reach them. Now, remember that after omega, ordinals split, and these numbers are no longer cardinals. They don't refer to a greater amount than the last cardinal we reached, but maybe they can take us to one. Wait. What are we doing? Aleph null? Omega? Come on, we've been using these numbers like there's no problem, but if at any point down here you can always add 1. Always. Can we really talk about it, this endless process, as a totality, and then follow it with something? Of course we can. This is math, not science. The things we assume to be true in math are called axioms. And an axiom we come up with isn't more likely to be true if it better explains or predicts what we observe. Instead, it's true because we say it is. It's conscequenses just become what we observe. We are not fitting our theories to some physical universe who's behavior and underlying laws would be the same whether we were here or not. We are creating this universe ourselves. If the axioms we declare to be true lead us to contradictions or paradoxes, we can go back and tweak them or just abandon them altogether, or we can just refuse to allow ourselves to do the things that caused the paradoxes. That's it. What's fascinating, though, is that in making sure the axioms we accept don't lead to problems, we've made math into something that is, as the saying goes, unreasonably effective in the natural sciences. So to what extent were inventing all of this or discovering it, it's hard to say. All we have to do to get omega is say let there be omega. And it will be good. That's what Earnest Zermello did in 1908 when he he included the axiom of infinity in his list of axioms for doing stuff in math. The axiom of infinity is simply the declaration that one infinite set exists: the set of all natural numbers. If you refuse to accept it, that's fine. That makes you a finitist, one who believes only finite things exist. But if you accept it, as most mathematicians do, you can go pretty far. Past these, and through these. Eventually we get to omega+omega, except we've reached another ceiling. Going all the way out to omega+omega would be to create another infinite set, and the axiom of infinity only guarantees that this one exists. Are we going to have to add a new axiom every time we describe aleph null more numbers? No. The axiom of replacement can help us here. This assumsion states that if you take a set, like say the set of all natural numbers, and replace each element with something else, like, say, bananas, what you're left with is also a set. That sounds simple, but it's incredibly useful. Try this. Take every ordinal up to omega, and then, instead of bananas, put omega+ in front of each. Now we've reached omega+omega, or omega times 2. Using replacement, we can make jumps of any size we want, so long as we only use numbers we've already achieved. We can replace every ordinal up to omega with omega times it, to reach omega times omega, omega squared. We're cooking now. The axiom of replacement allows us to construct new ordinals without end. Eventually, we get to omega to the omega to the omega to the omega to the omega to the omega and we run out of standard mathematical notation. No problem. This is just called epsilon naught. And we continue from here. But now think about all of these ordinals. All the different ways to arrange aleph null things. Well, these are well ordered, so they have an order type. Some ordinal that comes after all of them. In this case, that ordinal is called omega one. Now, because, by definition, omega one comes after every single order type of aleph null things, it must describe an arrangement of literally more stuff than the last aleph. I mean, if it didn't, it would be somewhere in here. But it's not. The cardinal number describing the amount of things used to make an arrangement with order type omega one is aleph one. It's not known where the powerset of the naturals falls on this line. It can't be between these cardinals, because, well, there aren't cardinals between them. It could be equal to aleph one. That belief is called the continuum hypothesis. But it could also be larger. We just don't know. The continuum hypothesis, by the way, is probably the greatest unanswered question in this entire subject. And today, in this video, I will not be solving it, but I will be going higher and higher to bigger and bigger infinities. Now, using the replacement axiom, we can take any ordinal we've already reached, like say, omega, and jump from aleph to aleph all the way out to aleph omega. Or, heck, why not use a bigger ordinal, like omega squared, to construct aleph omega squared? Aleph omega omega omega omega omega omega ome... Our notation only allows me to add countably many omegas here, but replacement doesn't care about whether or not I have a way to write the numbers it reaches. Wherever I land will be a place of even bigger numbers, allowing me to make bigger and more numerous jumps than before. The whole thing is a wildly accelerating feedback loop of ambigony. We can keep going like this, reaching bigger and bigger infinities from below. Replacement and repeated powersets (which may or may not line up with the alephs) can keep our climb going forever. So clearly, there's nothing beyond them... right? Not so fast. That's what we said about getting past the finite to omega. Why not accept, as an axiom, that there exists some next number so big no amount of replacement or powersetting on anything smaller could ever get you there? Such a number is called an inaccessible cardinal, because you can't reach it from below. Now, interestingly, within the numbers we've already reached, a shadow of such a number can be found: aleph null. You can't reach this number from below, either. All numbers less than it are finite, and a finite number of finite numbers can't be added, multiplied, exponentiated, replaced with finite jumps a finite number of times, or even powerset a finite number of times to give you anything but another finite amount. Sure, the powerset of a milinillion to a googolplex to a googolplex to a googolplex is really big, but it's still just finite, not even close to aleph null, the first smallest infinity. For this reason, aleph null is often considered an inaccessible number. Some authors don't do this, though, saying an inaccessible must also be uncountable, which, ok, makes sense, I mean, we've already accessed aleph null, but remember, the only way we could is by straight up declaring it's existence axiomatically. We will have to do the same for inaccessible cardinals. It's really hard to get across just how unfathomable the size of an inaccessible cardinal is. I'll just leave it at this: the conceptual jump from nothing to the first infinity is like the jump from the first infinity to an inaccessible. Set theorists have describes numbers bigger than inaccessibles, each one requiring a new large cardinal axiom asserting it's existence, expanding the height of our universe of numbers. Will there ever come a point where where we devise an axiom declaring the existence of so many things that it implies contradictory things? Will we someday answer the continuum hypothesis? Maybe not, but there are promising directions. And until then, the amazing fact remains that many of these infinities, perhaps all of them, are so big, it's not exactly clear whether they even truly exist, or could be shown to, in the physical universe. If they do, if one day, physics finds a use for them, that's great. But if not, that's great, too. That would mean that we have, with this brain, a tiny thing a septillion times smaller than the tiny planet it lives on, discovered something true outside of the physical realm. Something that applies to the real world, but is also strong enough to go further, past what even the universe itself can contain or show us or be. And as always, thanks for watching.
Another interesting fact about trans finite ordinals is that arithmetic with them is a little bit different. Normally, 2+1 is the same as 1+2. But omega+1 is not the same as 1+omega. 1+omega is actually just omega. Think about then as order types. One thing, placed before omega, just uses up all the naturals and leaves us with order type omega. One thing places after omega requires every natural number, and then omega, leaving us with omega+1 as the order type.